The ancient Greek philosophers...remained more faithful to the Idea of the philosopher than their modern counterparts have done. “When will you finally begin to live virtuously?” said Plato to an old man who told him he was attending classes on virtue. The point is not always to speculate, but ultimately to think about applying our knowledge. Today, however, he who lives in conformity with what he teaches is taken for a dreamer. Kant
Friday, April 29, 2011
God in a Coma
Today we talked about symbols and the generative power of symbols. I started to think how the symbols fit into a symbolic order, and through this symbolic order Christianity has defined and redefined itself on a basis of the power inherit, or lack of power, in the symbolic rituals of the church. So, my definition for the symbolic order comes out of Lacan: The social world of linguistic communication. intersubjective relations, knowledge of ideological conventions, and the acceptance of law (which Lacan calls the "big Other").
The example of Prof. Layne's son talking about symbols relates to this order. The child in consumed by language and accepts the rules, norms, and ideological consciousness of a certain society. Through this acceptance of the symbolic order, Simon (Prof Layne's son) is now able to relate to and deal with others and the authority they posses. Lacan gets a little messy when he starts pulling the symbolic order from the Oedipus complex, but even through dealing with this Oedipus complex, the name of the father, a likeness to Christianity and the conception of God as father arises. When I say the Name of the Father I mean that which mediates your desire and communication through restrictions and law--think of the Freudian superego. Language as the mediator of the symbolic gives us the human act par excellence, originally founded on the existence of the world of the symbol, specifically on the laws and contracts. Even in using the phrase par excellence I make a philosophical point through some sort of symbolic authority. Why do I even say par excellence in my pseudo french accent, when I could just as easily say it is the quintessential. By using the phrase par excellence I am taking from a linguistic terminology that symbolically represents an intellectual. I become what I want to be through the words and the symbolic authority I give to language I use and how I relate to it by relating to others. I want others to see me as a philosophical power, and the way they can perceive me in this way is through the words I use to paint a picture of myself.
Anyway, that tangent was going on for too long. The symbolic order in Christianity broke down during the Reformation, and a need to reinvent God and his rituals were called for. It seems like a lot of people in this class like Nietzche, and I think he realized this lack of symbolic authority of the Church in his proclimation, "God is Dead." God is Dead isn't a call for atheism, but we are given a break from the taditional Christian ideology and are introduced to a new form of belief. The thesis "God is Dead" is only one part of a two-fold thesis: "God is Dead" and "Christianity has survived the Death of God." Looking at the survival of Christianity despite the death of God can help to elucidate just what type of ideology has been functioning since the reformation.
Nietzche's affirmation concerns a symbolic God. The inherent power of God is stripped from the rituals of Christianity and we are left with a "dead God" we must power ourselves. In this death of the symbolic we can find the two formulations of God that have been functioning throughout the history of Christianity. There is the God of scientists, philosophers, and theologians, and there is the God of Job, Jacan, and Abraham. The first God functions as an ontological God within and the throughout the symbolic order of linguistics, law, and ideology; the God of Abraham functions as the Symbolic God--it is the excess of the symbolic which leads to Nietzche's death of God. The God referred to in the affirmation "God is Dead" is the God that powers the symbolic. This powerless God is robbed from the traditional Christian rituals and belief and in this void we find Christianity replacing God in the power of the symbolic.
The Reformation was a way for the Chruch to try to re-activate God in a new way that could survive the death of the symbolic God. Once rituals become powerless, new forms of worship begin to spring up without having to rely on a symbolic master. The power of the master was now in the hands of the people, and with this power new forms of prayer are no longer contingent on rituals.
The problem of the symbolic lack of power manifests itself as the empowerment of those who were once enslaved. This can also be seen through the Hegelian master-slave dialectic, which at its core claims that the master/slave power/powerless relationship is equally contingent on both parties. The lines between master and slave are ultimately blurred. Rituals that produce nothing due to the absence of the symbolic God shows us how the invisible scaffolding of our consciousness, our moral conception of life and will to believe, affirms this master-slave dialectic within the Christian fath. Using religion as a crutch is key to the survival of Christianity despite the "DEATH OF GOD." Using religion as a way to diminish your self and as a way to produce a sense of alienation as means to raise yourself up into the religious sphere is captured by the typical Christian rhetoric of "I am a sinner but in God I am saved." In this proclamation Christianity is able to elevate itself from a false sense of self worth into assimilation with God. This gives an excellent example, AN EXAMPLE PAR EXCELLENCE, of fetishistic disavowal at work after the "death of God": I know very well that the symbolic God is gone from the rituals and that I have to take the place of God by becoming my own God, but I nonetheless act as though the symbolic God still functioned as the generative power in the rituals and beliefs I uphold.
The discovery of God as a "power" is a major reason why Christianity was able to survive the death of God. Before the Reformation, the symbolic rituals created a way for people to connect to the God that is "beyond" our world. The rituals acted as a way for the two realms of existence, the earthly and the heavenly, to meet. Once the symbolic God was lost from the rituals, the God functioning as "power" takes on a whole new meaning. The way to reach "beoynd" into the other realm of existence is utterly unattainable. The symbolic no longer acts as the quilting point between realms, but it does feed on infinite passion to attain a higher level of being through religious experience. The new power no longer functions as generative but as accumulative. This accumulation of power created God again after the Reformation by keeping God at a distance. To get in touch with God we must function as passion for God. But this is too much philosophy for one blog post.
Ultimately, I am not trying to paint an atheists interpretation of Christianity. I actually think that the similarities between fundamentalist Christians and atheists are scary. The modern atheist can look at the proclamation "God is Dead" and find within it something he/she can support, but within this support there has to be an unconscious belief in God. This unconscious belief affects the modern atheist just as much as the conscious belief that God is dead, in the sense that there is a space in which God dwells. The atheist is a subject presenting him/herself as a tolerant hedonist dedicated to the pursuit of happiness, beauty, pleasure--a profound and naive romanticism maybe?--and their unconscious is the site of prohibitions: what is repressed is not illicit desire or pleasure, but suppression itself.
Hopefully you read all of that. Class isn't boring, it is just hard for me to give a synopsis of what happened without going off on tangents.
Thursday, April 28, 2011
Pagan Influence on Christianity
Wednesday, April 27, 2011
Unjustly Condemned
Saturday, April 23, 2011
A "scientific" look at justice
Friday, April 15, 2011
Conceit to Knowledge
Limitless and the Unity of Existence
Wednesday, April 13, 2011
Desert Island Books
Dialogue has various different parts: matter, form, nature, soul, intellect, and good. Digging deeper into these various aspects of the dialogue, I started to wonder about typical reactions to art and how "art consciousness" has shifted greatly since the Neo Platonists and today.
Here comes the exposition!
I am a musician and I appreciate when people enjoy the music I make, who wouldn't? But one thing that I have noticed, when describing art--be it a book or song--people like to use the terms "interesting" or "boring" when asked their opinion. For some reason this really annoys me. I think describing a piece of art as interesting or boring lends itself to a naive approach towards/understanding of art.
Looking at the various parts of dialogue used by Proclus, the categories boring and interesting seem to be out of place;indeed, they are not even present. What does it mean for something to be boring or interesting? (Apparently Hegel thought it was not a compliment to call something interesting) How do we experience boredom or interest? It seems to me that the interesting and the boring are both presuppositions of one another; two psychological categories that rest in the emotions and not in any sort of objective. The vicissitudes of these feelings prove their solipsistic nature--surely bespeaking the solipsistic milieu of art. Also, these feelings seem to stand in for concepts such as "the beautiful" or "the ugly." The way we register the interesting or boring is also interesting (ha). An interesting/boring object finds itself in our attention, we take cognizance of the object and then just as easily we let it go passing it off as boring or interesting. The effect doesn't last any longer than it takes for me to perceive, it only lasts as long as I am subject to the interesting/boring object, and only in the sense that I am sitting in church bored, but once I leave church I never dwell on this boring experience again. The same thing can be said about an interesting experience. The notion of the interesting arises when our conception of truth is no longer connected to art. Nowadays we connect truth to science.
I will figure out some more stuff to say about this in the next few days. Gotta get started on that paper!
I started wondering this when I found this website that invited its users to provide interpretations for the rap lyrics of various songs. Some could high light a section of the song and if it the artist used a lot of figurative language, someone could break down what was being said in layman's terms and allow others to talk about how their interpenetration differed from the one provided. And when I read through the meanings of particular verses they were taking away my first instinct was to say that they were wrong and missed the point. But since it is their opinion who am I to say they were wrong? And I found myself wondering if any neo-platinous would be able to say that the meaning one takes away from a text is wrong. Maybe the only wrong interpenetration would be to conclude that there is no meaning and leave the text lifeless.
Tuesday, April 12, 2011
Class Synopisis April 11th
"We are simply the universe experiencing itself"
The Eternal Nature of Texts
Monday, April 11, 2011
Ancient Philosophy in Hegel
Class Synopsis Friday April 8
We began class on Friday by reviewing Platinus, being sure to cover the major parts of Platinus’ theories that will be built upon by the later Neo-Platonists. The ones that seemed to stick out the most were Platinus’ monism (his belief that all is in all) and his theory about the One, Intellect, and the Soul. For this, we spent more time going over the distinctions between the three main parts and how they relate to each other. Specifically: the One being pure unity that looks at the Intellect, the Intellect is being that looks at the Soul, and the Soul being all. It is important to note that the reason why the soul cannot go beyond itself is because it is already all so there is no further for it to look. If it needed to look any further it would mean that the Soul is imperfect rather than perfect unity. From there we made a transition to other Neo-Platonists by way of how each philosopher posited that one could come upon unity.
Platinus believed that there were two paths to unity. One could get to unity by either faith or by way of knowledge. The next philosophers that we covered split greatly upon those lines. Porphry (232 AD in Athens) believed strongly that knowledge was the only way to get to the one. He rejected the allegorical truths and theurgies and instead believed that contemplation was the only way to get to the One. Conversely, Iamblicus (250-326 AD) believed the exact opposite. This was because he posited that the Soul was so descended that it knows the external world to much. He thought that religious rights are necessary for a person to turn inward and thus find unity. Additionally, he came up with the idea that aside from the monads (One, Intellect, and Soul) he thought there were more increments between the three which he called henads. A good example of this being the parts to the intellect: the intelligible- the objects of thought, the intelligible intellect- the thinking process, and the intellect- which had the ability to contemplate all these things. The henads would be very important to Proclus.
Thursday, April 7, 2011
Class Synopisis April 6th
How to talk about The One
Wednesday, April 6, 2011
The One is Disney World
Title aside, I just want to type out some of the Plotinus' ideas in my own words, and with the use of discursive reasoning seek the multiplicity in unity.
The one thing that I really like about Plotinus is his use of relata and relations. He talks about how we can come to understand universals and particulars through a homogeneous unity. The individual is presented against this unity as an alterity, but an alterity that is only distinguishable through the possession of something denied to universal (I want to call this concept/Plotinus wants to call this Genera). What is this something that makes the particular stand out from the whole? I would guess it is the relationship between the subject and the object, the way in which the relata and relations make particulars and universals distinguishable only through the other. I can't have a concept of dog if I have only experienced one dog, but at the same time I can't understand dog without that first particular dog experience that is eventually supplemented by more dog experiences leading to a dog concept. There is a potential problem in this understanding of relata and relation based on a holistic view.
Things can only become individuals by means of how they relate to other things, but how could there be any objective relation at all? Maybe Plotinus would posit the One as the solution, but then that would make this issue an ontological one. Perhaps it is an epistemological issue. We can only grasp what things are through relations and through our subjective experience. This epistemological issue seems to have a strong footing in phenomenology, especially that of Merleau Ponty, in the sense that our knowledge or conception of the truth is limited to our ability to grasp the truth at a given time. This ability to grasp the truth is perhaps synonymous to our ability to grasp the One, but taking into account individual differences among people, different capacities would deny any Absolute, One, or graspable Totality. Where phenomenology went "wrong", in breaking things down to their essential structures and examining things in the "lived world", the Phenomenologist doesn't take into account Plotinus' ideal world and the sensible world as a unity and they are thus estranged. If the ideals are just useless simulacra symbolizing objects in the world, then the phenomenologist did not go wrong at all, they just took the good part (sensible world) and did away with the ideals. Perhaps Plotinus' whole system is, to quote Paul Elmer More, "a meaningless answer to an impossible question raised by a gratuitous hypothesis." But at the same time, a big part of me loves everything he says and can truly see how things become individuated through relations. The problem might be an ontological one instead of epistemological, or both problems are irrelevant and there is no raison d'etre (I've never studied French but it makes it sound more philosophical) of objective relation.
I was thinking that the diagram of the one, intellect, soul could be easily appropriated to the centralized power of Disney World and the layout of the maps, if we conceive of both as a sort of brain.
Somewhat random aside--Adventureland is Frontierland are located on the left side (masculinity) and Fantasyland and Tomorrowland are located on the right (femininity). What this has to do with Plotinus, I haven't figured it out, but you can force anything if you use enough discursive reasoning.
Tuesday, April 5, 2011
Plotinus Review for Wednesday
For Plotinus, it seems to me that unity is being, and that could tells us something important about The One. It is by the virtue of unity that beings are beings; he uses a slew of arguments about its role. As soon as we say that something is this or that, then we attribute unity to it.
Ex. A
X is y.
In example a, we’ve attributed unity. Don’t bother with x is; if we can predicate something, then we might know Being, and in turn The One. But as Plotinus wrote, “We can see the totality of things when we look inside.”
For Plotinus, neo-Platonism was about virtue. We practice philosophy so that the soul can turn inwards towards The Divine Intellect and know The One. But although Plotinus has given us a clear path towards the unity, descending in an unbroken succession of stages from The One, The Divine Intellect, and The Forms therein through Soul, he did not write systematically like our charts on the blackboard. Instead, he studied in Alexandria for decades until finally exploding with treatises of his own. Turning inwards seems to be a process.
In Plotinus’s sixth ennead, The One or the Good is beyond the reach of human thought or language, and though we can talk about it, this insistence is to be taken seriously. What we know is that it is the supreme existence, no predicates need-be-applied. It is more, not less than mind. And in this way Plotinus seems to me to be dogmatic at first.
According to the ancient Greeks, the Unity of Virtue is a well-known tenet. And especially with Plato we find that Virtue is the way to The One. In Platonic thought, resurrected in Plotinus, all the apparently different virtues—piety or temperance—refer to different aspects of the same single property. With Aristotle, however, having virtue is a matter of having a character that disposes you to do the right thing in the right way, at the right time, to the right person, for the right reason. More, one needs to know what’s important to discern if the costs are worth suffering for what benefits. In some sense for Aristotle, virtue requires knowledge to reach The One or Nature or Eudaimonia, as he refers to it. Since different virtues concern different spheres of activity, the knowledge most centrally required for one virtue will differ from the knowledge most centrally required for another.
I like discursive reasoning. Reason brings us to knowledge. As Bertrand Russell once said, “philosophic contemplation, when it is unalloyed, does not aim at proving that the rest of the universe is akin to man. All acquisition of knowledge is an enlargement of the Self, but this enlargement is best attained when it is not directly sought.” The One just seems too good to comprehend, or rather, too good to be true. The primary object of Plotinus’s philosophical activity is to bring his own soul and the souls of others by way of The Divine Intellect to union with The One. But is the free will free to choose not to create? Plotinus believes that all must exist in unity; it seems we are already one.
Plotinus realizes in the sixth ennead that The One, the Being of the Particular, is a manifold, and that Unity cannot be a manifold; therefore, there must be distinction between being and unity. He posits: “Above all, unity is The First, but Intellectual Principle, Ideas and Being, cannot be so; for any member of the realm of Forms is an aggregation, a compound, and therefore—since components must precede their compound—is a later. The Unity cannot be the total of all things.”
Unity is paramount to our ascent to The One. But by not correctly identifying the target, we miss that, which is The Good. We should aim for Reason. Those whom existence comes about by chance and automatic action and is held together by material forces have drifted far from the concept of unity and The One.
Sunday, April 3, 2011
The Philosophy of Eclecticism
To me the philosophy of Eclecticism seems like a cop-out. I find it hard to believe that all philosophies, as different as they might be, can be tied into one— forced together in some sort of “natural” way, gathered, sewn together— without being downsized. I feel as if Eclectics are just little the middle person in the argument who agrees with both sides, saying that both arguments are right in some way, just so that they won’t have to think to hard about solving the problem. I know that this school of thinking developed because there were no new philosophies coming out and everything was falling into repetition, but I would rather repetition than submission. I believe that it would be better to continue being Epicureans, Stoics, Pythagorean, Aristotelian, etc. than just abandoning logic and metaphysics, putting everything into a big bowl, mixing it up, and saying “this is what I believe!” There is no reason or sense in substituting one set of logical foundations for another; this leaves philosophy shallow and weak. This philosophy can also be interpreted as weak because of its lack of a purpose. Yes, it unified the philosophies but what ultimate question was it trying to solve? Or was it just trying to make everyone from Rome to Greece happy (appeasement of the masses)? I honestly don’t know but hope to find out. Some of the theories presented by this philosophy, especially those on the soul, seem to have some worth and seem to be very complicated to understand (I have come to learn that the more complicated the theory that the better the concept turns out to be in the end) so this philosophy seems worthy of further investigation. I just hope that I can understand the explanation of the soul given by Plotinus because I think that that would be something interesting topic to talk over with a stranger on the streetcar when there is a delay.